The multiculturality of mathematics

Terezinha Nunes

Department of Educational Studies

University of Oxford

Most people would readily agree that mathematics learning involves using logic and most mathematics educators today would accept that mathematics is a cultural product – so, learning mathematics is learning to master a cultural invention. Both of these are appealing ideas but they can be seen as conflicting: logical principles should be universal and cultural inventions are not. In this paper, I will try to show how these ideas can be made compatible by working with the notion of reasoning systems. I will then explore the notion of reasoning systems in three contexts of mathematics learning: learning to count, using counting to solve different arithmetic problems, and translating (or rather failing to translate) between different representations for mathematics.

In exploring these examples, I will be working with some assumptions, which I want to make explicit from the start. First, I will assume, following the Piagetian tradition, that children's logical reasoning has its origins in their actions. This assumption is used in the design of the studies I will describe, in which children are asked to solve problems and the way they organise their actions is taken as an indication of their logic. Second, I will assume that the mathematical representations that they use are culturally provided, and have to be integrated into their reasoning system in order to be used. It does not matter for this discussion how the representations are learned; the argument is only that they are used well only when they are assimilated into a reasoning schema. Finally, I will be proposing that, once these representations are assimilated into a reasoning schema they affect the way it works, usually by increasing its power but also by structuring the way in which we deal with information. This means that, once some representations become part of the system, they direct our interpretation of new information and our problem solving efforts in specific ways. When there are alternative representations for the same situations, we may not easily move between them – but it would be to our advantage to do so.

What are Reasoning Systems?

Systems theory was applied to reasoning both by Piaget and the Russian developmental psychologists in the first half of the twentieth century. Piaget and the Russian developmental psychologists were attempting to solve the same problem and envisaged systems theory as the solution. The problem they were trying to solve was the mind-body problem. The problem is easily understood by considering the contrast between biological and higher mental functions.

Biological functions are typically carried out by specialised organs. For example, digestion is carried out by the digestive system; breathing by the respiratory system. Biological functions involve a constant task performed by the same mechanisms leading to an invariant result. If we consider breathing as an example, the task is to bring oxygen to the cells in the body. This is accomplished by an invariant mechanism: oxygen is received by the blood cells and transported to all the cells in the body. The invariant result is that the cells receive oxygen.

In contrast, higher mental functions are not carried out by a specialised organ but through the co-ordination of different actions. They are carried out by functional systems. According to Luria's definition, in functional systems “a constant task [is] performed by variable mechanisms bringing the process to a constant result” (Luria, 1973, p. 28). I will take one of Luria's examples to make this point. The first one is ‘remembering'.  It is easy to be misled into thinking that we have a specialised organ for remembering: the brain. But Luria points out that remembering involves functional systems rather than a single biological unit. Imagine it is your partner's birthday and you want to remember to buy some flowers before going home. Your task is to remember to buy flowers. You can accomplish this through a variety of means. You can simply repeat this to yourself many times until you think it is now impossible for you to forget. You may tie a knot around your finger: as you don't normally have a string around your finger, this will remind you to buy the flowers. You might write it down to help you remember – on your palm, where it will be very visible. Or on a yellow sticker, for example, and paste it on your wallet. Or you may type it into your electronic diary and set an alarm to go off just before you leave your office. These variable mechanisms can be used with the same end: to recover the information. No single biological unit can account for all the different mechanisms you may call upon when trying to remember something, and most of us do not rely on “natural” memory to organise our lives: we have diaries and write into them what we are supposed to do when and we use Powerpoint when giving seminars to help us remember what we wanted to say next. Human memory is limited but humans don't depend on what they can remember without help: our memory system is open in the sense that it can work with external aids, and we are empowered by learning to use external memory mechanisms that, in conjunction with our natural memory, allow us to remember better. Many cultural aids work in ways that help us surpass the limits of our memory.

The second example I want to explore relates to external mechanisms that help us surpass the limits of our perception of time. A thought experiment might help understand what I mean by this. Suppose I ask someone: when are we meeting tomorrow? If this is a culture without clocks, what type of answer could I have? How does the answer change when the question is asked in a culture that has clocks? In a culture without means of measuring time the answer must differ because it will be based on perceptions related to time whereas in a culture with clocks we will use the measurement of time to provide our answer. In a culture without clocks, our idea of how long is the day and how long is the night might depend on whether it is winter or summer; in a culture with clocks, we define a day as lasting a certain number of hours even if it gets dark earlier in the winter and later in the summer. So our conception of time becomes independent of our perceptions – even if we cannot perceive the difference between 10 o'clock and 5 past 10, we can still look at the clock and tell the other person: “you are late”. Our conceptions of time in cultures where we rely on clocks are shaped by the measurement of time – we think of the day as having 24 hours, the hours as having 60 minutes, the minutes as having 60 seconds as if this is what time is. But we could think of the same cycle has having 86,400 seconds, organized into minutes of 100 seconds, and might say nothing about hours. In this case, instead of saying “I will see you at 10 o'clock tomorrow”, we would say “I will see you at 360 minutes tomorrow”.  Having a way of measuring time, we incorporate it into our reasoning system about time.

Reasoning systems are open systems: they allow for the incorporation of tools that become an integral part of the system. Vygotsky suggested that what is most human about humans is this principle of construction of functional systems that allow activities to be mediated by tools. He termed this ‘the extra-cortical organisation of complex mental functions' to stress that these functional systems cannot be reduced to the brain.

Even the most elementary mathematical activities are carried out by functional systems. Solving the simplest addition problem, for example, involves a reasoning system. Paraphrasing Luria: we have no specialised organ for addition. If asked to solve the problem ‘Mary had five sweets and her Grandmother gave her three more; how many does she have now?', a pupil can find the answer through a variety of mechanisms. The pupil can put out five fingers, then another three, and count them all. The pupil can put out just three fingers and count on from five. The pupil can recall an addition fact, 5+3, and use no fingers. In this were a large number, the pupil might decide to use a calculator. These are variable mechanisms that bring the invariant result of finding the answer to addition problems.

For educators, one of the most significant features of higher mental functions is that they are open systems: the variable mechanisms – which are often created through the incorporation of tools - can be replaced by taking into the system something new from the environment. When a mechanism is replaced with something new, the system changes. To use Piaget's terminology, when a child assimilates something new into his or her reasoning system, the system accommodates to a new way of functioning.

Many of the changes that we introduce into children's mathematical reasoning systems in school are representational: we teach children to represent things in new ways which empower them. These new ways of representing, in turn, have an impact on their reasoning system, and open to them new possibilities of reasoning. This is not, of course, all that happens in mathematics learning, but it is a very important part of what happens in mathematics learning. The idea of reasoning systems will be illustrated here with three examples: understanding counting, using counting to solve different types of problems, and different systems for handling addition and subtraction and intensive quantities.

Counting

In order to learn to count appropriately, children must be able to follow three principles: to establish a one-to-one correspondence between number labels and objects, to have a different number label for each object to be counted (otherwise the one-to-one correspondence principle would be violated) and to keep the number labels in a fixed order (otherwise counting the same number of objects might end up on a different number label on different occasions). This means that counting 1,000 objects would require that children learn 1,000 different words in a fixed order – a major task for our poor memory. Over the course of history, cultures have solved this problem by using a base-system for counting. With a base system, we do not have to remember the counting words, we learn how the counting system works, and can generate new counting words which we have not heard before.

Base systems could be used simply as a series of words that are easy to generate. However, they represent a new idea, which goes beyond one-to-one correspondence: they represent the additive composition of number. Children may, at first, use a counting system with a base without grasping this principle, and only later grasp the idea of additive composition that is part of a base system. We have for many years used the Shop Task as a simple experiment that shows whether the children understand additive composition. In this task, children are asked to pretend that they are buying things from the experimenter and offered coins that they can use to buy these things. Under the one-to-one correspondence condition, the children are given many 1p coins and ask to pay, for example, 13p, 17p, 23p and 25p for different toys. All they need to do is to count the coins one by one until they reach the desired number. Our studies have shown that children in their first year of school in the UK (mean age in our last study 5 years 10 months, N=112) have no difficulty in counting the desired amounts of money in this one-to-one correspondence condition, and reach almost 100% correct responses. Under the additive composition condition, the children are given coins of different values: to pay 13p and 17p, they are given one 10p coin and 9 1p coins, and to pay 23p and 25p they are given one 20p coin and 7 1p coins. Their performance in this second task is quite different: 51% of the children give no correct response (in six items), counting the 10p and 20p coins as ones, even though they know the value of the coins. They do not use the coins of different values to compose quantities even though they can count up to those quantities when they are given only 1p coins. We conclude that these children are using a base system as if it were a simple string, which only required one-to-one correspondence principles. Over time, and also with the support of teaching, the children's reasoning accommodates to the additive composition principle embedded in the system, and through this the children gain more power in the use of the counting system.

Much research has shown that the regularity of the counting system affects how easily the children learn to count (e.g. Miller & Stigler, 1987; Nunes & Bryant, 1996) and also how easily they grasp the idea of additive composition (e.g., Nunes & Bryant, 1996; Miura et all, 1988). This research can be summarised by examining one of our comparisons betweenTaipei and>Oxford children. The Chinese counting system is quite regular, and the words for 11, 12 etc are the equivalent to ten-one, ten-two etc. The words for 20, 30 and the other decades are literally translated as two-ten, three-ten etc. 21, 22 etc literally translated as two-ten-one, two-ten-two etc. This regular system, which represents the idea of additive composition so clearly, contrasts with English, where the count words in the teens are irregular. Note, however, that neither system gives any clues to the idea of additive composition when the children have to pay 7p using a combination of five plus two ones. So, if the Taiwanese children perform better when producing these combinations of coins, this shows that they are not merely matching words to coins but that they have understood the principle of additive composition. We gave the 5-year-old children the Shop Task using the relevant currency in each country and varying the denominations of coins: some trials used one ones, others used combinations of five and ones, and other used combinations of ten and ones. Within this range, theTaipei and>Oxford children did not differ when paying for toys in the Shop Task when the coins were all ones. However, they differed significantly when they had to use the additive composition principle. The>Taipei children made very few errors (8% only) in the combinations of ten and ones, where their system can help them with the idea of additive composition very directly, and a few more (20%) when they had to count combinations of five and ones, where they have no direct help from the system. In both cases, they performed significantly better than the >Oxford children, who gave wrong answers to 56% of the trials that used combinations of ten and ones and to 46% of the trials that used combinations of five and ones.

Our conclusion is that the reasoning system that children form in order to count depends on logic – the correspondence principles mentioned earlier on and the additive composition principle, when using a base system – and also on the culturally devised tool for counting, a system of number labels. By learning the system of number labels in English or in Chinese, children overcome the limits of their natural memory, because they can generate the number labels by using the logic of the system. If this logic is more transparent in the system, they can understand it more quickly.

Using counting to solve different types of problems

From the preceding examples, it could appear that counting is related to addition in a straightforward way – that knowing how to count and how to add are almost the same thing and that there is nothing more to counting than adding. In order to make the point that counting is a tool in arithmetic in general, not just a basis for addition, it suffices to consider a few examples where children's logic guides the way they organise materials in order to count and to find the answer to different types of problems. In these examples, the children's logic guides the way they manipulate objects and what they count, once they have represented the problem.

The first example is a contrast between two subtraction problems. Both are change problems but in one the missing value is the end result and in the other the missing value is the change. A change problem with result unknown would be: a boy had 6 marbles; he put them in his pocket and went out; he had a hole in his pocket and 4 marbles fell out; how many did he have when he got home? The same problem with the change unknown: a boy had 6 marbles; he put them in his pocket and went out; he had a hole in his pocket and some fell out; when he got home, he had 4 marbles left; how many fell out? In both problems, the child can use the materials to represent the total, represent the change, and the result. In the first problem, the child removes 4 marbles and counts the ones left. In the second problem, the child counts 4, which are the end state, and has to conclude that the others are the marbles left in the boy's pocket. Although the problems seem so similar when the child acts the problem out, the missing end state problem led to 75% correct responses in our sample of children in their first year of school whereas the missing transformation problem led to 35% correct responses. The child has the same tools but different logical moves are required.

The second example is the use of counting to solve multiplication problems. We gave children the following multiplication problem: in each house in this street (four houses are drawn) live three dogs. How many dogs live in this street? In order to solve this problem, children count by pointing to the houses – not in one-to-one correspondence but in one-to-many correspondence because they point and count three times as they point to each house. Children's performance in these problems is surprisingly good: 58% of the children's responses (to 5 problems) were correct when they were in their first year of school (5y10m old, N=112).

These different ways in which children use counting illustrates how their logic guides the way they count in order for them to solve problems. Knowing how to count is a tool, necessary but not sufficient, to solve problems, much like having a watch is necessary but not sufficient for children to be able to tell the time.

Translating between tools: addition and subtraction calculation ability

Children first solve addition problems using their fingers to represent the objects in the problem. The principle used by the pupils' reasoning system in this representation is one-to-one correspondence: one finger represents one sweet; one counting word is tagged to one finger; the last counting word indicates the number of sweets. There is an important logical move underlying this way of solving problems: if children understand that they can count fingers to solve problems about sweets, they understand that the referent (finger, sweet) does not affect the result of an addition operation. In other words, 1 + 1 = 2 regardless of what the numbers represent. 

Later, children are able to “count on”: when solving the problem “A girl had 5 sweets; her Granny gave her 3; how many does she have now?”, they replace the use of five fingers with the word ‘five' by itself. This change seems to be a representational change: instead of one finger for each sweet, one word – five – represents all five sweets at the same time. This small change has a huge impact on the reasoning system: whereas children have a limited number of fingers, number words continue indefinitely on. A system with fixed limits becomes much more powerful because its limits are removed by a change in tools.

There are some indications in our research that this representational change is related to children's understanding of additive composition. A study carried out by Katerina Kornilaki gives strong support to this idea. She gave children different types of tasks, which involved counting with different levels of representation of one of the addends – the other addend was always visibly represented. In the first type of task, the children were asked to say what where the totals of two sets which were represented visually and remained represented visually the whole time. So they could simply count all the visible objects. In the second type of task, adopted from Steffe and his colleagues (1982), the children were asked the sum of two sets, but one of them was counted and then hidden – for example, the children were told that a girl had six coins, saw the coins, and these were then put into a wallet. Then the girl was given three coins, which remained visible; the children were asked how many coins the girl had now. Hidden addend tasks, as Steffe found, could be solved either by count all or count on procedures. When counting all, the children pointed to the wallet inside which there were coins, and counted up to the six, and then went on to count the three coins outside. When counting on, the children simply said “six” and counted on. The third type of task was our Shop Task. The difference between the tasks is in the representation of the first addend: it is either completely visible, or visible at first but then hidden, or encoded in a coin of a value larger than 1. The tasks clearly vary in level of difficulty: the first being is easiest and the third, the Shop Task, the most difficult. An analysis of the children's performance across tasks showed that only children who were able to count on in the hidden-addend task succeeded in the Shop Task – but not all of them did so: counting on was a necessary but not sufficient move to understand additive composition. A change in the representational tools – from the expanded representation in one-to-one fashion to the compressed representation of the Shop Task has an impact on the children's performance because of the extra logical move, additive composition, required to succeed in the Shop Task.

The understanding of additive composition is a powerful idea and seems to be the basis for addition and subtraction of larger numbers in oral arithmetic. The reasoning system of oral arithmetic can develop in the absence of knowledge of written arithmetic. In >Brazil, these two systems exist as independent cultural practices: oral arithmetic is used in street markets and the informal economy in general and written arithmetic is used in schools. The contrast between the two systems illustrates how the same logical principles create different reasoning systems when the cultural tools used by the person are different. Our previous work in >Brazil has shown that young people and adults with little schooling may have very good calculation ability in the oral mode and poor calculation ability in the written mode. This difference is not explained by differences in logical principles used to calculate using oral arithmetic in comparison to written arithmetic: it is explained by the differences in the cultural tools being used. The analysis of children's calculation procedures in oral and written arithmetic shows that both rely on the logic of the additive composition of numbers and the associative property of addition. If 17 is the same as 10 plus 7, and 13 is the same as 10 plus 3 (additive composition), the sum of 17 plus 13 can be found by adding the tens, adding the ones, and then putting it all together. These are the principles used when children carry out additions and subtractions orally and also the principles used in the written algorithm. However, because the tool for representation changes – oral or written numbers – the reasoning systems used in calculation are different. They can be integrated but they can also exist in isolation from each other. Our work shows that children who are expert at oral arithmetic may nevertheless find it difficult to use the same reasoning principles to calculate with the written system (a discussion of this research can be found in Nunes, Schliemann and Carraher, 1993) and vice versa – many people can use the written system to calculate but not the oral system. Translation between oral and written calculation systems is not simple. However, it is possible to envisage a system that coordinates both of these, which would be more powerful and flexible than either one.

Translating between tools: ratio and fractional language in intensive quantities

The final example I will use here is the representation of intensive quantities and how it affects children's understanding of intensive quantities problems. Intensive quantities are quantities defined by the ratio between two other quantities. For example, the taste of orange juice is dependent on the ratio between orange concentrate and water. The probability of an event occurring (for example, to draw a blue marble from a bag) is dependent of the ratio between the favourable and non-favourable cases (the marbles of other colours). Many (though not all) intensive quantities can be represented numerically by ratios or fractions. The mixture of orange juice can be expressed as one cup of concentrate for two cups of water or 1/3 concentrate. The probability of drawing a blue marble can be described as one blue marble for two white marbles or as 1/3. Both forms of representation involve proportional reasoning when making comparisons – for example, between the taste of orange juice of two mixtures or the probability of drawing a blue marble from two bags with a mixture of white and blue marbles.

Despina Desli compared children's ability to solve some intensive quantity problems when the information was presented to them in ratio language or in fraction language. The children were given problems like this one: A girl made three cups of orange juice by mixing one cup of concentrate with two cups of water. The juice tasted perfect so the next day, when she was going to make juice for a party, she wanted it to taste exactly the same. She had to make 18 cups of juice. How many cups of concentrate and how many cups of water should she use?  This problem is couched in ratio language; half of the children had the problem presented to them in this way. The other half had the problem presented in fraction language: A girl made three cups of orange juice by using a mixture of 1/3 concentrate with 2/3 water. The juice tasted perfect so the next day, when she was going to make juice for a party, she wanted it to taste exactly the same. She had to make 18 cups of juice. How many cups of concentrate and how many cups of water should she use? Half of the children in each group had manipulatives, which they could use to help them solve the problem – little cups coloured in orange and white. The other half of the children only had paper and pencil. The children were assigned randomly to these conditions.

All the children in the study, aged 8 to 10, had been taught in school about the fractions used in the problems. The 8- and 9-year old children who were presented with the problems in ratio language performed significantly better than those who were presented with the problem in fractions language; the difference was not significant for the 10-year-olds. Because the children had been randomly assigned to these testing conditions, it is reasonable to assume that the language differences explain the differences in performance. It is possible that children can start to develop their understanding of proportionality by using a ratio representation without being able to connect it to a fractional representation – and only later achieve this coordination.

An analysis of children's strategies suggested that this is the case. When the problems were presented in ratio language, 30% of the children were able to use correspondence reasoning, and replicate the correspondences until they reached the total amount. For example, one cup concentrate with two cups water makes 3 cups; 2 cups concentrate with 4 cups water would make 6 cups – and so on, until they had the desired 18 cups total. The logic of correspondences develops early and children can start to solve proportions problems by using it. When presented with the information in fractions language, it is not so easy to use this schema. Because children do not find it easy to translate back and forth between the two ways of representing problems, even though they could have used correspondences to solve the problem, very few (4%) of those who had the problem presented in fractions language thought of this solution.

Conclusions

These examples were used to show how the idea of reasoning systems, which are open and can accomplish the same aim through different mechanisms, can coordinate the use of logic with different tools that are culturally developed. The tools can both empower the user, by helping overcome the limits of memory and perception, for example, and also will influence how the user conceptualises mathematical problems. Because different representational tools can highlight different aspects of the same situation, users who can coordinate them are more flexible. However, this coordination might not take place easily and spontaneously: one of the aims of mathematics teaching should be to help users coordinate systems that seem to work independently but relate to the same logic.


References

Kornilaki, K. (1999). Young children's understanding of multiplication: A psychological approach. PhD thesis, Institute of Education, >University of London.

Luria, A. (1973). The working brain. Wandsworth (UK): Penguin.

Miller, K. F., & Stigler, J. W. (1987). Counting in Chinese: cultural variation in a basic skill. Cognitive Development, 2, 279-305.

Miura, >I. T., Kim, C. C., Chang, & Okamoto, Y. (1988). Effects of language characteristics on children's cognitive representation of number: cross-national comparisons. Child Development, 59, 1445-1450.

Nunes, T. & Bryant, P. (1996). Children doing mathematics.>Oxford: Blackwell.

Nunes, T., Schliemann, A. & Carraher, D. (1993) Street mathematics, school mathematics. New York: >Cambridge University Press.

Steffe, L. P., Thompson, P. W., & Richards, J. (1982). Children's Counting in Arithmetical Problem Solving. In T. P. Carpenter, J. M. Moser & T. A. Romberg (Eds.), Addition and Subtraction: A Cognitive Perspective (pp. 83-96).Hillsdale, NJ:>Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society. In M. Cole, V. John-Steiner, S. Scribner & >E. Souberman (Eds.).  The development of higher psychological processes.Cambridge MA:  >Harvard University Press.


Agenda